Saying Grace, Adriaen van Ostade, 1653
There is something paradoxical about that deepest and most original source of social organization—namely, the giving and receiving of gifts. To give, one must do so graciously, and without expectation of return. After all, to give for the sake of return is to make an investment, which is precisely not to give. Likewise, to receive a gift well, one must be grateful—again, not because we have to in some sort of mechanistic sense, but because it is a characteristic response of good will.
But of course it is also true that a beneficiary gives with something like an operative expectation of return. If I buy lunch for my friend, I would be surprised and probably even miffed were he to accept without responding in a manner, even if it is only by expressing his thanks. When a child receives a gift from her grandmother, she is expected to respond gratefully—even and perhaps especially if she is not excited by the gift. Barring some sort of artificial ideological commitment, we think it natural to teach children gratitude.
Still, as philosopher Claudia Card puts it, “A duty to be grateful sounds like a joke.” There is a constitutive ambiguity in the giving and receiving of gifts, one that is not present in more formal or impersonal contexts in which the conditions of right return are specified precisely. To be grateful is necessarily unnecessary, which is appropriately confusing, and the spontaneity of gift exchange is uniquely vulnerable to awkwardness and even pain. “You shouldn’t have” is only one bizarre way in which such ambiguity manifests in Anglophone cultures.
Now, we might be forgiven for not caring too much about this, to relegate the matter to an unimportant, if unfortunate, inelegance of polite society. But this would be a mistake. Graceful giving and grateful receiving are distinctively human arts, integral to our life together in ways that are invisible to us, without reflection.
The great Roman philosopher Seneca offers the most influential extended treatment of the mystery of gratitude in all of Western philosophy in his first-century letter, On Benefits. “Among the many and diverse errors of those who live reckless and thoughtless lives,” writes Seneca to his peer and well-known benefactor Aebutius Liberalis, “almost nothing that I can mention . . . is more disgraceful than the fact that we do not know how either to give or to receive benefits.”
This is not hyperbole, at least not in the author’s own self-understanding. Seneca is quite serious that ingratitude is a pernicious, fundamental evil—a failure of personal character, friendship, and religious devotion. In fact, wagers Seneca, “all [crimes] spring from ingratitude, without which hardly any sin has grown to great size.” Ingratitude is born of a “partial view of ourselves, by greed, or by jealousy,” all species of a failure to understand the reality that “the immortal gods have held—still hold—us most dear, and in giving us a place next to themselves.”
But what is it about gratitude that makes its consequences so dire? Seneca’s answer—an answer that would reverberate in intellectual cultures far beyond his own—in a classic argument from Book IV of On Benefits:
God has given [humanity] two things, reason [ratio] and fellowship [societas], which, from being a creature at the mercy of others, make him the most powerful of all; and so he who, if he were isolated, could be a match for none is the master of the world. Fellowship has given to him dominion over all creatures; fellowship, though he was begotten upon the land, has extended his sovereignty to an element not his own, and has bidden him be lord even upon the sea; it is this that has checked the assaults of disease, has made ready supports for old age, has provided solace for sorrow; as a help against Fortune [fortuna]. Take away this fellowship, and you will sever the unity of the human race [unitatem generis humani… scindes] on which its very existence depends.