In his 1974 Massey Lectures, the literary critic and philosopher George Steiner characterized the void in Western civilization, after the decline of religion, as a “nostalgia for the absolute.” Once theology and transcendence no longer served as the foundation of society and the basis of human conviction, then “this desiccation, this drying-up, affecting as it did the very centre of Western moral and intellectual being, left an immense emptiness. Where there is a vacuum, new energies and surrogates arise.”1 Steiner primarily examines three such surrogates that attempted, but ultimately failed, to fill the void: Marxism, Freudian psychoanalysis, and Lévi-Straussian structural anthropology, all of which he terms mythologies. In his usage, a mythology connotes a system of thought that claims “totality” in explaining man and his relation to the world; has a distinct inception and history, which includes a canon, an orthodoxy, and heretical offshoots; and creates its own language and its own set of symbols and rituals. Indeed, as nontheistic (or antitheistic) as such ideologies might be in their substance, they nonetheless mimic their opponent and offer “a kind of substitute theology,”2 and a kind of prophetology, or in the words of Steiner (and many others), “secular messiahs.”
Yet European messianic secularism would prove catastrophic; history attests to a tragic lethality that was not incidental to the surrogate doctrines. Marx and Freud, for example, have entries in a compelling account of ideologues who were, as the book is titled, Architects of the Culture of Death.3 The authors demonstrate that it is precisely the messianic and totalizing nature of Marxism and of Freudian philosophy, based on their radically reductionist humanisms, that engendered “death cultures.” With his paradigm of “scientific” materialism, Freud reduced the human being to a mere biological being, devoid of any spirit or soul, and he significantly minimized the centrality of reason and judgment in the motives behind human action, thereby dismissing the ethical imperative altogether. But to eliminate the soul and the moral life is to inaugurate a culture antagonistic to life. And given his immense influence in the modern history of Western civilization, the pernicious effects of Freud’s surrogate faith had a widespread and lasting impact. As for Marx, his program combined rage against class exploitation and injustice, dialectical materialism, “rational” atheism, and a summons to violent revolution, while his salvific promise included liberation, a cure for man’s alienation, and ultimately a utopian earthly paradise of societal cooperation without the hierarchy of classes. It was an atheistic religion that captivated the hearts of the oppressed masses by igniting their religious instinct, which was no longer grounded in a theistic and spiritual worldview, and ultimately destroyed their lives and that of countless others. As the Muslim theologian Abdal Hakim Murad notes, the secular messiahs of European modernity have been fully “unmasked as lethal fantasists,” and the Hegelian worldview of “progress through synthesis” that informed many totalizing mythologies has proven flawed and false; such developments, along with other factors, have now left the continent in a state of existential melancholy.4
Related to the culture of death, post-religious modernity can also be described as an age of nihilism and disenchantment, both of which inform the nostalgia. An important articulation of the disenchanted new world is Max Weber’s “Science as a Vocation” (the first of his Vocation Lectures). Redolent of Hume’s discourse on the is/ought distinction, Weber’s lecture underscored a defining feature of the age: modern science, and its ground of naturalism, could provide no answers to the fundamental questions of existence, purpose, and morality. Absent now from the public sphere were “the ultimate and most sublime values.” In a climactic moment, Weber proclaims: “If anything at all, the natural sciences are more likely to ensure that the belief that the world has a ‘meaning’ will wither at the root!”5 Despite the great advances of technological and scientific “progress,” the fate of nihilism seemed inevitable. In a disenchanted and flattened world, in which an abstracted “intellectualization” (or a posture thereof) presides over a civilization lacking a celestial criterion, where do people turn? For Weber, the solution lies in what appears to be a hazardous subjectivism; he concludes his analysis with the recommendation that each intellectual discover and follow the “inner spirit” (daemon) that “holds the threads of his life.”6
Arguably, Ivan Turgenev’s 1862 novel, Fathers and Sons, popularized the term nihilism in the discourse of modernity.7 Its main character Bazarov exemplifies the implications of scientific naturalism in his self-proclaimed nihilism, which is discussed in an early dialogue between the “fathers,” or older generation, and Arkady (the protégé of Bazarov, both of whom represent the “sons”). The elders understand it to denote the acceptance of nothing or the respect of nothing, whereas for Arkady, it denotes the rejection of any and all principles accepted “on faith.” They respond that, without such principles, it is difficult to envision how one could intellectually walk or even breathe, followed by the warning, “Previously there used to be Hegelians, now there are nihilists. Let’s wait and see how you get on in a vacuum, in airless space.”8
But if Turgenev set in motion the term, it was Nietzsche who shook Europe with the concept, along with a significant philosophical (though apparently anti-systematic) unpacking of it. With his famous madman shouting in the marketplace to proclaim the “death of God,”9 Nietzsche diagnoses the post-religion West as a culture that has denied God’s existence and thus, without realizing it, has denied all absolutes, such that “nothing necessary remains in one’s hands.”10 Even Enlightenment reason and science, given the universality of their claims, must give way with the dissolution of absolutes. Indeed, a century later, Lyotard would declare the collapse of metanarratives in knowledge claims and thus the transition from modernity to a postmodern age; no longer rooted in a grand narrative of seeking truth, science was instead comprised of a multiplicity of small narratives engaged in what Wittgenstein called “language games.”11
What, then, of the meaning of human action? For Nietzsche, the dictates of morality are not sent down from heaven but merely reflect the human psyche, specifically, man’s “will to power.” The way forward is to move, as expressed in the title of one of his works, “beyond good and evil,” because the ancient designations of good (denoting power and pride) and bad (denoting weakness and meekness) were inverted by Abrahamic religion to, respectively, the notions of evil (as sin) and good (as virtue and piety). In Nietzsche’s world, the latter terms are mere designations of a “slave morality” invented by the impotent, in revolt and spiteful resentment against “master” warrior elites.12 The collapse of metaphysics allows Nietzsche to provide this genealogy of morals from a historicist approach; with a pessimism reminiscent of Schopenhauer (who greatly influenced him), he proceeds to “philosophize with a hammer”13 and deconstruct absolutes, one after another. Good and evil are now reduced to values, which are relative or perspectival. Nietzsche boldly asserts, “There are no moral phenomena at all, only a moral interpretation of phenomena”14 (again, echoing Hume’s is/ought dichotomy). Later, he continues to use his proverbial “philosophical hammer” to smash ethical truth, this time to reveal its alleged bedrock of feeling: “In short, moralities too are only a sign-language of the emotions.”15 Objective, universal, absolute Truth does not exist and hence cannot be pursued, let alone ground the claims and concerns of mankind, for they inhabit “a world whose essence is will to power.”16
Of course, given the incoherence (and madness) of pronouncing such absolute judgments to deny all absolutes, the discerning mind recognizes in Nietzsche’s discourse an extreme pathology, of both reason and the spirit, albeit dressed in the guise of psychology and philology and despite his discourse being at times insightful. Still, the underlying pathology was intense and fatal. Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, too, are listed in the aforementioned chronicle of death-culture architects, where they are categorized as “Will Worshippers”: Schopenhauer for his metaphysics of cruelty and evil that characterizes the underlying “will” of atheistic Nature, and Nietzsche for replacing the metaphysics of theistic truth, goodness, and beauty with an anti-metaphysical humanism rooted in man’s will to power.17
The philosopher Allan Bloom comments on Nietzsche’s reduction of ethical realism to value relativism as follows: “In short, Nietzsche with the utmost gravity told modern man that he was free-falling in the abyss of nihilism. Perhaps after having lived through this terrible experience, drunk it to the dregs, people might hope for a fresh era of value creation, the emergence of new gods.”18 Bloom later describes how this worldview evolved in the American context, in which nihilism has been (in his view) more of a “pose” or pervasive cultural attitude, accompanied by what he regards as a largely impoverished education:
There is a whole arsenal of terms for talking about nothing—caring, self-fulfillment, expanding consciousness, and so on, almost indefinitely. Nothing determinate, nothing that has a referent…. There is a straining to say something, a search for an inwardness that one knows one has, but it is still a cause without an effect…. American nihilism is a mood, a mood of moodiness, a vague disquiet. It is nihilism without the abyss.
Nihilism as a state of soul is revealed not so much in the lack of firm beliefs but in a chaos of the instincts or passions. People no longer believe in a natural hierarchy of the soul’s varied and conflicting inclinations, and the traditions that provided a substitute for nature have crumbled. The soul becomes a stage for a repertory company that changes plays regularly—sometimes a tragedy, sometimes a comedy; one day love, another day politics, and finally religion; now cosmopolitanism, and again rooted loyalty; the city or the country; individualism or community; sentimentality or brutality. And there is neither principle nor will to impose a rank order on all of these.19
Renovatio is free to read online, but you can support our work by buying the print edition or making a donation.
Browse and Buy